http://www.andrepiet.nl/holle_aarde/links.html
Dit forum staat op alleen-lezen. Je kan hier informatie zoeken en oude berichten terugvinden, maar geen nieuwe berichten plaatsen.
Meer informatie op bijbel.startpagina.nlMostafa Abdelkader and the Geocosmos
With the marginal exception of Euler’s and Leslie’s proposals, the hollow Earth
remained entirely outside of the scientific community’s consideration or even awareness
(except as a novelty; see Sexl 174-176) until 1982, when Mostafa Abdelkader proposed a
mathematically-based rationalization for the geocosmos, one of the mystical forms of the
hollow Earth idea that arose in the 19th century. To say that Abdelkader reintroduced the
idea to the modern literature of science is true. But to say that it had any noticeable effect
whatsoever on the world of mainstream science would be an overstatement. The reasons
lie in the ways that the practice of science as a conservative social construction, evolved
during the nearly three hundred years separating Halley from Abdelkader.
In 1692, nothing, really, was known of the nature of Earth’s interior, the boundary
between the nascent modern, materialistic world view and the entrenched superstition of
Christianity was vague, and the scientific community had not developed the system of
peer review that lies at the heart of modern scientific practice. Halley was able to publish
his theory in one of the premier scientific organs of the day, in part because of the valid
empirical data it contained (his list of compass variations held considerable value for
navigation) but also because of the general state of scientific knowledge at the time and
because his standing within the Royal Society meant that he could probably have
published pretty much anything he pleased.
By 1982, modern geoscience had evolved, matured, and developed a robust
description of Earth’s (non-hollow) interior based principally on evidence from seismic
waves. That understanding was developed and is maintained by the necessarily
conservative process of peer review, and in 1982 there were few venues where it is
possible to submit an idea as radical as the hollow Earth to serious review and
consideration by an audience of scientific peers. One of those was the journal
Speculations in Science and Technology.
Speculations in Science and Technology was one of a handful of serious-minded,
professional, scientific journals that have been established to examine topics and issues at
the fringe of modern science’s range of acceptable inquiry (a notable peer in this niche is
the Journal of Scientific Exploration). There are doubtlessly many in the scientific
community that would deny the journal all validity, and a great many more who don’t
even know it ever even existed. But Speculations was published from 1977 until 1998 by
respectable publishers (Elsevier and then Kluwer, both powerhouses in academic
publishing) and its contributors, reviewers, and editorial board members were generally
(though not always) practicing scholars, some of them quite distinguished, in legitimate
fields of science and philosophy. Nonetheless, the journal’s stated purpose was to provide
a forum for speculation on ideas that are outside the scientific mainstream (though not too
far: topics related to UFOs and Extra Sensory Perception, for example, were not
accepted).
So, while Halley’s theory entered mainstream scientific discourse at its core,
Abdelkader’s geocosmos did so at its fringe. Moreover, it arrived there from an origin in
religious mysticism. To appreciate Abdelkader’s proposal in its appropriate context, it is
useful to briefly consider the trajectory of hollow Earth ideas as they evolved among
pseudoscientists and mystics during the 19th and 20th centuries.
The conception of Earth as a hollow sphere in an otherwise Copernican universe
(as invoked by Kircher, Burnet, Halley, Euler and Leslie) is the most intuitive conception
of the hollow Earth. The geocosmos, in which Earth’s surface occupies the interior shell
of a hollow sphere containing the entire universe, requires considerably more
imagination. Its modern form originated in the mind of Cyrus Reed Teed, an Eclectical
physician and practicing “electro-alchemist” from Utica, New York (see Kafton-Minkel
and Gardner for accounts of Teed’s remarkable history). In 1869, Teed had a mystical
experience in which he received the revelation that he was the living incarnation of
Christ. He also came to understand that the Copernican conception of the universe was
backwards. According to Teed’s “Cellular Cosmogony,” Earth is a hollow sphere that
contains the entire universe. We live on the inside surface.
Teed changed his name to Koresh, established a religious cult (“Koreshenity”)
that grew to be national in scope, and eventually established a utopian commune Florida.
There, adopting the outer appearances of scientific inquiry, Teed and some of his
followers organized the Koreshan Geodetic Survey and conducted an experiment to
prove Earth’s concavity. Using a specially-constructed apparatus dubbed the
“rectilliniator,” the Survey spent five months in 1897 patiently moving the device along a
six kilometer-long stretch of beach. Not surprisingly, the results of the survey were
exactly as Teed predicted—Earth’s surface proved to be concave (Gardner, Fads… 24).
While it is not clear whether or not Teed was consciously aware of it or not, his
geocosmos reflects the alchemical conception of the hermetic egg, the rotundum within
which, as Nelson (137) notes, microcosm and macrocosm— “cosmos, globe, and human
soul”—converge. Its genius lies in the fact that reconstitutes the geocentric universe (with
the comfortable reassurance that Earth, and thus humanity, occupies a privileged place in
a cosmos that is not only finite, but bounded at a humanly meaningful scale) in a way that
is still consistent with contemporary astronomy, provided one doesn’t look too closely.
Teed ensured that close examination would be unlikely by couching his theory within an
excruciatingly complicated cosmology and adopting the strategy of describing it in
impenetrable, scientific-sounding prose.
Teed died in 1908 (Koreshenity—including the commune of Estero, Florida—
persisted into the early 1950s), a decade or so before a German pilot named Peter Bender
came across several copies of the Koreshan’s Flaming Sword in a stack of American
magazines in a French prisoner-of-war camp during World War I. Bender was won over
by Teed’s geocosmos. After the war, he returned to Germany where he developed and
promoted the idea, which he dubbed the hohlweltlehre (“hollow Earth doctrine,”
sometimes also referred to as hohlwelttheorie). He abandoned the religious aspects of
Koreshenity and simplified Teed’s byzantine labyrinth of concepts and ideas to a simpler,
though still bizarre, mechanism to reconcile observed nature with the concave conception
of Earth.
Bender’s hohlweltlehre like other hollow-Earth theories before and since,
attracted its share of supporters, though none from within the ranks of mainstream
astronomers or Earth scientists. He was, however, able to muster enough political support
to manage two tests of his theory. The first of these was an attempt, in 1933, to build a
rocket and launch it straight up into the sky. If Bender’s hollow-earth idea was correct,
the rocket should have crashed into the opposite side of the planet. Instead, it failed to
launch and crashed a few hundred meters from its launch pad.
The second test came about through Bender’s connection (dating to his World
War I pilot days) with Hermann Göring and the interests of a group of German Naval
Research Institute officers who sought methods for locating enemy ships based on fringe
ideas such as pendulum swinging and the hohlweltlehre. These officers gained approval
to send an expedition to Rügen Island (in the Baltic Sea) to try and detect British ships
using powerful telescopic cameras pointed upwards across Earth’s concavity. Bender
claimed that the apparent convexity of Earth’s surface is due to the refraction of visible
light passing through the atmosphere. If Earth’s surface were concave, the officers
reasoned, photographs taken using infrared filters (infrared radiation is not refracted by
the atmosphere) should show parts of the North Atlantic and Baltic, and the positions of
British ships in those waters could be known. The failure of the Rügen Island experiment
proved embarrassing to the Nazi High Command, and Bender, his wife, and some of his
followers perished in death camps as a result.
Another German, Karl E. Neupert, published a pamphlet titled Mechanik des
Aethers, Gegen die Irrlehren des Kopernicus (“Mechanics of the Ether: Against the
Erroneous Teachings of Copernicus”) in 1901, and a book-length treatment titled simply
Geocosmos in 1942. Neupert collaborated with Bender until his unfortunate demise, and
after the war, he and another of Bender’s follower, Johannes Lang, continued to
publishing booklets and magazines on the subject promoting the idea. Neupert died in
1949, but Lang carried on, publishing a journal called Geocosmos into the 1960s. Neupert
and Lang, like Teed and his followers, distributed their writings widely, and at some
point, one of these copies caught the attention of Mostafa Abdelkader, who alone among
those who have encountered it was in a position to re-introduce the hollow Earth concept
back into the realm of mainstream science.
The key to the geocosmos model lies in reconciling the geometry of an internal
universe with observed phenomena such as the rising and setting of the sun and the
motions of other celestial bodies. Teed attempted this reconciliation by proposing an
absurdly complex clockwork model that invoked various gaseous layers within the
hollow of the planet and “refocalization” of the true Sun (which he said was light on one
side, dark on the other, and rotated like a beacon at the center of the universe) on the
upper layer of the atmosphere (Kafton-Minkel 94).
The simplest way to achieve such a reconciliation, however, is to abandon the
idea that light rays travel in straight lines, and have them travel in curves instead. The
simplest way to achieve this curvilinear behavior, in turn, is to simply perform a
mathematical mapping of the Copernican cosmos “outside,” into the geocosmos “inside.”
This is precisely what Abdelkader did, using a mathematical manipulation called
inversion to map the cosmos into the sphere of Earth.
Inversion is a geometric transformation that is useful for converting certain types
of otherwise intractable (or exceedingly complex) geometrical systems into forms that are
amenable to mathematical analysis. It is especially useful for transforming unbounded
regions into bounded ones; making the infinite finite, in other words. The geometry is
quite simple. To invert a plane with respect to a circle, for example, we simply map every
point outside the circle to a corresponding location within it. To invert the universe with
respect to a sphere, we simply map every point to some corresponding point within the
sphere, which is what Abdelkader proposes we do with respect to the sphere of Earth. But
this simplification both obscures the beauty and undermines the primary weakness of
Abdelkader's proposition. It is worth considering his proposition in some detail.
Abdelkader begins his paper with the proposition that Earth’s surface can be
considered a sphere (it is not, actually, but the slight equatorial bulge can be safely
ignored) of fixed radius with its center located within an absolute rectangular coordinate
system having x, y, and z axes. All points outside Earth’s surface can be denoted by X, Y,
Z and those inside the sphere by x, y, z. Abdelkader notes that in the Copernican system,
Earth rotates about its axis and revolves around the sun which, in turn, rotates around the
center of the Milky Way galaxy, and so on. By establishing the coordinate system in
relation to Earth’s center, however, Abdelkader has subtlety dispensed with the
Copernican universe and reestablished geocentrism: “We shall regard the earth as at
rest, so that all celestial objects are moving in the coordinate system (xX, yY, zZ)” (81).
Having prepared us, as a magician would, by framing the situation just so, Abdelkader
announces that he will perform the crux move of his trick: “In the following section, the
whole of space will be subjected to a purely mathematical mapping taking infinite space
outside the earth’s surface into its inside, and vice versa” (81). What follows are the
necessary mathematical manipulations.
The inversion operation is illustrated in Figure 2. Every point outside the sphere
of Earth maps to an analogous image point within it. “Thus,” Abdelkader explains (82),
“the earth’s surface is mapped into itself (with us living on the inside surface of a hollow
earth), all of outer space becomes embedded inside this hollow earth, with infinitely
distant points” mapping to the origin point of the sphere, and “objects such as stellar
galaxies and quasars distant several billions of light years, are shrunk to microscopic
size.”
After inversion, the moon, our closest celestial neighbor, maps to a sphere 955
meters across that circulates 6265 kilometers above Earth’s surface. The sun, on the other
hand, shrinks to about 2.5 meters across and recedes to a location just 253 meters from
the origin point (i.e. the center of the universe). Pluto shrinks to the size of a single
bacterium floating seven meters from the origin, while Alpha Centauri, the star closest to
our own Sun, becomes an infinitesimally small speck situated a mere millimeter from the
origin. Every other star and object in the cosmos, therefore, is contained in a sphere less
than two millimeters across that hovers 6371 kilometers above our heads.
Having inverted the Copernican cosmos to fit comfortably within Earth’s shell
(which becomes infinitely thick as a result of the inversion), Abdelkader goes on to
explore some of the implications of the transformation, first with regard to the shapes of
spheres and then the behavior of light. Because everything in the geocosmos shrinks with
distance from Earth’s surface, spherical bodies become slightly deformed in the direction
perpendicular to Earth’s surface (the Moon, for example, would be about one percent
smaller between the points nearest and furthest from Earth than it would be from pole to
pole).
The degree of deformation is relatively slight if we assume that the origin is, in
fact, a point. But Abdelkader notes that, while this assumption is perfectly acceptable in a
mathematical system, it is unrealistic in a physical one, so he substitutes a sphere of
arbitrary diameter for the origin point. If the radius of the origin sphere is very small
relative to the radius of Earth, the distortion is negligible. Larger radii for the origin
sphere, however, can result in a significant degree of distortion.
The changes in the behavior of light rays after inversion are perhaps the most
striking feature of Abdelkader’s model. In the Copernican cosmos, rays of light travel in
straight lines, as shown in 3A. Note that for an observer positioned where ray H intersects
Earth, E, (along the circle of illumination), the Sun would be visible on the horizon and
be seen as setting. For an observer positioned below ray J, it would be solar noon.
The inverse mapping preserves angular relationships, so that observers positioned
in the geocosmos would experience exactly the same phenomena as those in a
Copernican universe, as shown in Figure 3B. Ray H maps into e as ray h, and an observer
positioned at ray h’s intersection point would observe the sun on the horizon. Moreover,
because the Sun rotates around the origin, O, the observer would see it as setting, exactly
as does the observer in the Copernican cosmos (the Sun travels in a conical helix in the
geocosmos, which accounts for seasons). It is solar noon where ray j intersects Earth, and
halfway between solar noon and sunset below ray i. A person observing i would see the
sun as being somewhere between the horizon and the solar zenith at exactly the same
position in the sky as a person observing ray I in the Copernican universe.
Rays K and L do not intersect Earth in the Copernican universe and, assuming
they do not intersect anything else, will continue traveling to infinity. In the geocosmos,
however, k and l travel in arcs that lead back to the origin. The rays never actually reach
the origin, however, because the inversion operation affects not only the direction of light
rays, but their velocities as well. The speed of light is constant in the Copernican
universe, but variable in the geocosmos, ranging from ca. 3x109 cm/second at the surface
of e to zero at O.
The result of these conditions, Abdelkader notes, is that “all observations and
estimates of the size, direction and distance of any celestial object would lead to exactly
the same results” for an observer on the outside of Earth in a Copernican universe “and
his image observer inside, whether situated on or above” Earth’s surface (86).
Furthermore, as the case of the speed light illustrates, all physical laws that apply in the
Copernican universe can be inverted to apply in a geocosmos as well, provided we
invoke appropriate conditions to support them. The movement of Foucault pendulums
and the Coriolis effect, for example, are explained conventionally as effects arising from
Earth’s rotation about its axis. As Abdelkader notes, it is meaningless to attribute motion
to Earth in the geocosmos, but these phenomena can be explained in a geocosmos by the
rotation of the origin sphere (this, in turn, he attributes to an “all-pervading perpetual
cosmic force;” page 88). This isomorphism between the geocosmos and the Copernican
universe is a critical feature of Abdelkader’s hypothesis, because it creates a situation in
which it is impossible to empirically refute the geocosmos as a valid model of the
universe on the basis of observational tests.
The bulk of Abdelkader’s paper constitutes, as he puts it (87), “the purely mental
operation of geometrically mapping outer space…into the hollow earth…, a perfectly
legitimate process of thought” to which “nobody could raise the slightest objection.”
Though Abdelkader seems to have been unaware of it, Roman Sexl invoked the
hohlweltlehre in exactly the same vein in a paper on geo-chronometric conventionalism
published in 1970. Sexl used the hollow Earth to show that topology of space-time is
conventional, rather than intrinsic (he uses the example of “flatland”—c.f. Abbott—for
the same purpose regarding dimensionality). But Abdelkader has a larger goal in mind,
and he departs from the realm of idle mathematical curiosity in the last two pages of his
treatise. “Consider now” he entreats us “the hypothesis that our actual universe is the
finite and not the infinite ” (87; emphasis in
original).
Abdelkader supports his proposition by arguing that observational evidence
suggests that our universe is Copernican, provided we are willing to accept the untestable
assumption that “light is propagated in straight lines for billions of years, so that the
positions of celestial objects are in their observed directions…” (87). His point is not that
this is an unrealistic assumption, but rather that it is empirically untestable and therefore
the assumptions underlying the geocosmos are no more or less unreasonable than those
on which the Copernican model depends. So, Abdelkader reasons, given the choice
between two unfalsifiable models, both of which depend upon untestable assumptions
and yield identical observational data there is no reason to accept the Copernican view a
priori.
Abdelkader suggests that “there is no way of ascertaining the truth or falsity of the
hypothesis that our actual universe is except by digging a tunnel right
through the earth’s centre. … If our universe is , a tunnel 12,742 kilometres
long brings us to the earth’s surface again. If our universe is , nobody
knows what lies underground” (87). In fact, such a tunnel (if it were possible to dig one)
would not necessarily solve the dilemma. As the drill creating the tunnel receded from
the surface, it would become larger and larger, eventually becoming infinitely large and
infinitely far from the surface. At that point, it would likely emerge from the opposite
direction (some mathematicians and philosophers disagree on this point) and begin
shrinking as it approached the surface, emerging at a location antipodal to its starting
point.
There are, however, other grounds on which to reject the geocosmos, principally
its complexity and the privileged position in the universe that it ascribes to Earth. Martin
Gardner has discussed these objections in an essay entitled “Occam’s Razor and the
Nutshell Earth” (16). Occam’s razor dictates that, given a choice between two theories
with the same explanatory and predictive power, we adopt the simpler one. Complication
is to be tolerated only if it yields a commensurate gain in explanatory or predictive
power. Non-Euclidean geometry and Einsteinian relativity, for example, are more
complicated than their Euclidean and Newtonian counterparts but provide greater
explanatory and predictive power at astronomical scales. The same is true of quantum
theory at the subatomic level. Abdelkader’s geocosmos carries a high cost in
mathematical complexity (Figure 4) but, as noted above, there is no way to empirically
determine which model, geocosmos or the Copernican universe, provides the better
description of the cosmos.
So what does the geocosmos provide in return for the computational burden it
imposes? For Abdelkader, the answer is a sense of psychological comfort. At the end of
his paper, the detached language of mathematics and minimalist rhetorical presentation
give way to prose that conveys a barely-contained sense of angst that is rare in the
published discourse of modern science. The first paragraph of his conclusion bears
quoting in its entirety:
For one who dogmatically insists on believing the unprovable hypothesis
that light propagates in straight lines over distances of billions of lightyears,
the universe must be the universally accepted Copernican system. If
one is open-minded enough to get rid of one’s attatcment to this dogma,
then the only alternative universe is Geocosmos. The former, with its
incredibly gigantic stellar galaxies and other celestial objects distant
billions of light-years, and its stupendous energy sources, scattered
aimlessly throughout space, reduces the earth and the solar system to
nothing in comparison; whereas in the latter, the earth’s surface is the
finite boundary of the whole universe contained within it. Since both
universes are equally possible, there is no valid reason for astronomers,
astrophysicists, and other scientists to confine their attention exclusively to
the study of , totally dropping the competitive
out of their consideration. Probably the majority of these
scientists have never even heard of ; it is never mentioned in
the proliferating books on astronomy, either the technical or the popular
ones, as far as the author is aware. (88 emphasis in original)
For Abdelkader (like his Koreshan and hohlweltlehre forebears), the geocosmos
banishes the incomprehensible void of outer space to a speck contained within Earth’s
interior, simultaneously rendering the cosmos humanly comprehensible and restoring
Earth’s pre-Copernican place of privilege in the cosmos. If, as most mathematicians
believe, the idea of an inverted universe cannot be empirically refuted, is there really
anything wrong with this? Does it matter?
From a practical standpoint, accepting the geocosmos would have little or no
effect on most of us. We experience the universe as Euclidean space with Earth’s surface
or (occasionally) the Sun as our reference framework, and we can pass our entire lives
without ever having to take an Archemedian perspective that views the framework itself.
The same cannot be said for the “astronomers, astrophysicists, and other
scientists” Abdelkader lambastes for failing to give the geocosmos its due. The
geocosmos model simply does not solve any scientific problems they face, and pre-
Copernican nostalgia and apeirophobia are apparantly not widespread enough within the
space science community to justify the burden it would impose. Even if it were, the
geocosmos would not necessarily provide a cure. Abdelkader’s inversion banishes the
topology of the Copernican universe, but does nothing (except axiomatically) to
undermine the Copernican principle.
The Copernican revolution taught us that we should not assume that we occupy a
privileged place in the cosmos. Inversion does not suspend this principle except by fiat,
and as one of Gardner’s correspondents points out (On the Wild Side 21), even if the
geocosmos is a valid model, there is no reason to expect the universe to be inverted with
respect to our little planet. There are, for example, an estimated 1010 galaxies in the
known universe. Assuming that each of these contains 1011 stars, as does our own galaxy,
and that each of these stars is orbited by a mere ten spherical bodies (planets, their
moons, comets, asteroids, and small bits of rock or ice—any spheroidal body will do),
there must be 1022 objects in the universe (let us be clear here—this is a one followed by
twenty two zeros) to choose from. The probability that any one of them, including Earth,
is the preferred body is only 1/1022, which is vanishingly close to zero. Moreover, there is
no reason why the inversion must be done in relation to a physical body at all. It is
equally plausible to simply perform the inversion around an arbitrarily chosen spherical
region of space, in which case the choice of regions and spheres is limitless. Regardless
of which sphere we choose, if it is anything other than Earth, our planet becomes even
smaller and less significant than ever.
The only way to retain Earth as the preferred body is to simply assume
geocentrism, as Abdelkader has done. But if we are willing to indulge in this sort of
axiomatic reasoning, why not take the logic a step further, to egocentrism? If banishing
the extrasolar universe to a two-millimeter sphere provides relief from a feeling of
cosmic insignificance, then surely inverting the universe with respect to one’s own eye
(remember—any spheroid will do) must be more satisfying still.
This is truly an experiment that you can perform at home. You need not perform a
single calculation—simply declare that the cosmos is contained within your eye, and it is
done. Revel in knowing that you have given new truth (not to mention ownership) to
Walt Whitman’s claim “I am vast, I contain multitudes,” and no empirical test can refute
the proposition. Thrill to the fact that your brain is now the largest object in the universe,
and the question of what came before you and what will follow now have universal
importance. Experiment to your heart’s content, though it might be wise to keep the
knowledge secret, hidden away in your own little hollow world.
——————————————————————————–
Works Cited
Abbot, Edwin A. 1992. Flatland: A Romance of Many Dimensions. New York: Dover.
Abdelkader, Mostafa. “A Geocosmos: Mapping Outer Space Into a Hollow Earth.”
Speculations in Science and Technology 6 (1983): 81-89.
Burnet, T. The Sacred Theory of the Earth. (1690/91) London: Centaur Press, 1965.
Crowe, Michael J. The Extraterrestrial Life Debate, 1750-1900. Cambridge: Cambridge
University Press, 1986 (1999 Dover reprint).
DeCamp, L.S. and W. Ley. Lands Beyond. New York: Rhinehart and Co, 1952.
Drake, Ellen. Restless Genius: Robert Hooke and His Earthly Thoughts. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1996.
Gardner, Martin. Fads and Fallacies In the Name of Science. New York: Dover, 1957.
—– On the Wild Side. New York: Prometheus Books, 1992.
Godwin, J. Arktos: The Polar Myth in Science, Symbolism, and Nazi Survival. Kempton,
IL: Adventures Unlimited Press, 1996.
Halley, Edmund. “A Theory of the Variation of the Magnetic Compass.” Philosophical
Transactions of the Royal Society xiii (1683): 208-228.
—–. “An account of the cause of the change of the variation of the magnetical needle
with an hypothesis of the structure of the internal parts of the Earth.”
Philosophical Transactions of the Royal Society xvi (1692): 563-587.
Hooke, Robert. “Lectures and Discourses of Earthquakes and Subterraneous Eruptions,”
(1668-1700). Transcribed, annotated, and with an introduction by Ellen Tan
Drake in Restless Genius: Robert Hooke and His Earthly Thoughts. New York:
Oxford University Press, 1996.
38
Kafton-Minkel, Walter. Subterranean Worlds: 100,000 Years of Dragons, Dwarfs, the
Dead, Lost Races and UFOs from Inside the Earth. Port Townsend, Washington:
Loompanics Unlimited, 1989.
Kollerstrom, N. The Hollow World of Edmond Halley. Journal of the History of
Astronomy 23 (1992):185-192.
Leslie, Sir John. Elements of Natural Philosophy: Including Mechanics and Hydrostatics.
Edinburgh: Oliver and Boyd, 1829.
Nelson, Victoria. “Symmes Hole, Or the South Polar Romance.” Raritan 17 (Fall 1997):
136-166.
Peck, John W. “Symmes’ Theory.” Ohio Archaeological and Historical Publications 18
(1909), 28-42.
Sexl, Roman U. “Universal Conventionalism and Space-Time.” General Relativity and
Gravitation 1 (1970): 159-180.
Stanton, William. The Great United States Exploring Expedition of 1838-1842. Berkeley:
University of California Press (1975).
Symmes, John Cleves. Circular No. 1. Reprinted in Peck (30) and Kafton-Minkel (61).
Zircle, C. “The Theory of Concentric Spheres: Halley, Mather and Symmes.” Isis 37
(1947), 155-159.
Figure Captions.
(…)
Figure 2. Abdelkader’s inversion. Any point P outside Earth’s sphere is mapped to point
p inside the sphere according to the simple relation xX = a2 where x is the distance
between the surface E and p, X is the distance from E to X, and a is Earth’s radius (for
simplicity’s sake, Earth is considered to be a perfect sphere, though in reality it is slightly
flattened at the poles). We can obtain the distance x for any point P in the cosmos by x =
a2/X.
Figure 3. The behavior of light rays in a Copernican universe (3A) and Abdelkader’s
geocosmos (3B). Both diagrams are diagramatic only, and not to scale.
Figure 4. A ray of light passing through two points (X1, Y1, Z1) and (X2, Y2, Z2) follows a
straight line defined by the two equations in 4A. After inversion, its path is transformed
into a circle (or, if it intersects Earth’s surface, an arc thereof) passing through the origin
and defined by the equations in 4B. Based on Abdelkader’s equations 11-13.
——————————————————————————–
Om te beginnen moesten er voor je aanwezigheid hier biljoenen rondzwervende atomen op een complexe en intrigerend dienstbare manier zich samenvoegen om jou te scheppen. Dit is een ordening die zo ingewikkeld en bijzonder is dat het nooit eerder is geprobeerd en alleen deze ene keer zal bestaan. Gedurende de vele jaren die komen (hopen we) zullen deze minieme deeltjes zich zonder protest bezighouden met al die miljarden kundige, coöperatieve verrichtingen die nodig zijn om je te behouden en je de hoogst aangename, maar in het algemeen ondergewaardeerde toestand te laten ervaren die we het bestaan noemen… - Bill Bryson
hoe kan het dat we ons niet de hele dag door druk hoeven te maken of ons hart niet stopt met kloppen en of de longen het nog wel doen. Wat als alle atomen opeens ophouden met rond te zweven in ons lichaam? Onze nieren, de organen, ademhaling, gaan 's nachts door. Dat is niet zomaar het gevolg van atomen die toevallig gerangschikt zijn. Nee, er is god die alles in de hand houdt. Ook als we slapen.
Weet je zeker dat je deze post als spam wil rapporteren aan de beheerder?
Deze post wordt als spam gerapporteerd aan de beheerder van het forum. Bedankt!
Weet u zeker dat u dit topic wil verwijderen?